Why embryo selection for polygenic traits is wrong.

This week (May 20th 2019) has seen yet another splash by an American company offering a polygenic trait score on embryos including intelligence. This is wrong on a number of levels; ethically it is wrong to make this decision as an independent laboratory without broad societal buy in; scientifically it is wrong to imagine the ways we assess polygenic traits will translate into safe and effective embryo selection; for the specifics of IQ/Educational attainment trait this trait is so complex this is additionally unwise over and above any concerns.

I would not recommend it either as a member of society or as a genomic scientist. This blog aims to unpack this more.

Ethics

First off it is important to realise that as science progresses in biology – and in particular reproductive biology – we develop the possibility that we can perform actions that as a society we consider wrong. There is nothing new for this; for example, ultrasound scanning allows one to reliably sex foetus early on in pregnancy; however parental choice of sex of the child is either explicitly illegal or implicitly prohibited in most locations. As we learn more about genetics, we will be able to make more sophisticated choices of what we could do, but it is important that we make the decision about what we should do as responsible members of society.

This decision has to be made using processes set up inside each society; in practice this means under national legislation. I am both most familiar with and very comfortable with the UK’s Human Fertilization and Embryo Authority scheme (HFEA). This is a statutory body set up by the UK Parliament, with a variety of lay and religious members, as well as ethicists and scientists. The UK Parliament has made some possible schemes illegal (for example, reproductive cloning) but otherwise provides considerable latitude for the HFEA to make decisions. It is important that this body is has a majority of non scientists, and when the HFEA licenses a procedure the UK can be very confident it is medically safe, scientifically sound and ethically has broad support.

Each country has to arrange their own affairs, but I think there are some principles of best practice. One is that the scientists and clinicians are not self regulating here – it needs societal buy in. The second is that it is near impossible to handle this via national laws – laws are complex to change and near impossible to write with foresight for future science.

Science of polygenic traits

I am a longstanding genomic scientist, and have broad interest across many topics in genomics and genetics. Despite my cautious enthusiasm for using the genetics of polygenic traits in other medical spheres, in particular to potentially augment our understanding of risk of common diseases in adults, I do not think it is appropriate for embryo selection or assessment, certainly not without more research and potentially not for a long time. The main reason is that we have a high potential to cause harm, and only a small potential to mitigate bad outcomes. Stepping back – polygenic traits are traits where multiple places in the genome contribute to a trait (poly = meaning many, and genic meaning genes). This is well established genetic theory and practice since the 1930s (pre-dating the discovery of DNA). However, not only are these methods inexact but we simply do not know what other features are linked to the traits – the most sophisticated models deliberately do not attempt to localise the precise genomic locations to gain more predictive power. In a situation where one is doing something quite novel (selecting embryos from in vitro fertilized embryos) one simply doesn’t know what would happen. For example, it might be for some traits there are strong developmental aspects which mean the polygenic score we select on also contributes to development defects or to other features in an adult we did not anticipate. There is a big difference between scoring an adult who is alive and well, and selecting embryos for implantations. You might think I am being paranoid, but the history of animal breeding has shown many unforseen consequences of mating strategies; for example, selection of fast growing chickens lead at first to socially inept chickens who bullied / fought with each other when grown in flocks. This was recognised and eventually a multi-variate breeding scheme was put in place, but it could only be recognised by actually trying it. Selection of embryos on polygenic scores would be an experiment, and one in which we would have true unknowns; some of those unknowns having the potential to cause serious harm.

Some commentators cite the success of animal breeding schemes using genetics as supporting polygenic trait selection of embryos. This is misguided. Despite these schemes employing genetics (and similar machinery as polygenic risk scores, known as “Breeding Values” in the breeding community), the schemes are not the same as embryo selection from a random cross; animal breeding genetics gets its main benefit from selecting mates for breeding, not on selecting embryos of a random mating. I know of no animal breeding scheme which involves embryo selection for breeding traits (although embryo selection is used in the production of transgenic animals or selection of sex in elite breeding lines, and via this blog post I have learnt more about its use in plant and animal breeding). Furthermore, as discussed above, animal genetic breeding scheme are a cautionary tale of how things can go wrong as well as go right. The difference is that “failed” breeding choices in plant and animal breeding are simply discarded – this is not acceptable for humans. Anyone who is using plant or animal breeding as justification for the success of genetic intervention in humans simply does not understand animal breeding.

A further point which I almost feel it is so obvious it is not worth making, but reading some articles it does seem necessary. The amazing ability to directly edit genomes is of no relevance to this discussion. Polygenic trait “prediction” should perhaps be better stated as “interpolation” as what is happening is that we take an individual’s genome and try to estimate its phenotype using many many previous individuals phenotype and genotype. The most powerful methods to do this deliberately do not model any specific base pair changes (it ends up being statistically more advantageous to do so as our genome moves around broadly in blocks rather than specific bases); even when we try to estimate the precise bases involved at a particular location, the “blocky” nature of human genetics prevents us from ever being sure. So, although we can steadily improve our ability to use genetics for prediction, it is not in the way of using knowing the precise changes to make, and if we ever tried to do this it would, again, be an explicit experiment for polygenic traits (for monogenic or digenic traits with high penetrance alleles there is a different argument; in those cases it is extremely hard to imagine a scenario where currently licensed pre-implantation diagnosis would not work but genome editing would work).

Intelligence and Educational Attainment as polygenic trait

The genetics of intelligence and of educational attainment (how well people do at school) is a very complex topic; nevertheless some real progress has been made in particular over the last 10 years. This blog post is not the place to unpack the complexity of this trait (unsurprisingly … it is complex) nor the validity of the genetics – I recommend work from Stuart Ritchie, Paige Harden, Alex Young, Ian Deary and Robert Plomin as a selection of researchers in this field. My summary for this purposes of this blog post is that the genetics of IQ and educational attainment are real polygenic traits, but they are the sorts of traits one should be particularly careful of thinking about for embryo selection, over and above my generic concern above, and even when one is trying to focus only on “severe intellectual disability” end of the spectrum.

There are a number of scientific reasons why. The first is that these traits are hard to estimate and the non-random environment (the fact that schooling is different in different places even in relatively homogenous environments) coupled with localised genetics means it is hard to know whether one has “scrubbed” out this effect (cryptic population stratification). Again, the potential for selecting against perfectly reasonable embryos (and performing a procedure with risks) for no gain is present. The second is that around one third to a half of the genetic signal for intelligence / educational attainment (depending somewhat on how you construct the statistics) is due to parental environment; because each person’s genetics is also a reasonable good estimator of their parent’s genetics, genetic variants which influence parenting and via this, the child’s IQ/education show up strongly. This is fascinating research (note; the same techniques that find this do not show a strong effect of parental environment on other traits, eg, blood lipids or height) but means that estimating the tails has an additional major complication in trying to isolate the true “within individual effect”. Finally there are complex interactions between some deleterious traits (eg, autism) with educational attainment (there is a weak positive correlation) meaning that this trait in particular is complex to understand.

This is before one gets into the ethical considerations about how one should handle this trait, though if one is focused on the most severe disability end, this is at least justified. However, the obvious (and wrong) snake oil position is to imagine one can rank or significantly select for the top end of a continuous scale. All the problems with the trait are valid each end; more importantly a naive view of this will be that one can select from the top or bottom of the population distribution, whereas the main determinants in embryo selection will be the genetics of the father and the mother – one is bounded by these genetics (formally – a small variation around the mean of father and mother in the models used; in practice rarely goes outside of this expectation).

Summary

It is both my position as citizen in society (in my case, the UK) that one should not use embryo selection for complex trait behaviours and it is my position as genome scientist that this would be scientifically unsound to do so for any trait, in particular for IQ or educational attainment traits. It is worth considering what would be the closest thing to this that I could endorse. In terms of the science I can imagine (and I believe is licensed now) digenic (two locus) selection, and in the future I could imagine oligenic selection. Furthermore I could imagine a case of one or a small number of loci and a polygenic background, where there is differential advising and options to parents with “bad” polygenic backgrounds for a particular disease coupled with some higher effect size loci which could be treated (in effect) as monogenic diseases in their cases. Finally I can see severe behavioural difficulties with strong genetic basis in mono or oligenic as candidates for licensing. But these are growing the scope from the existing practice, and are a very very long way away from generic polygenic trait scoring for behaviours in embryos.